RICHARD SERRA: PERSPECTIVITY IN PERSPECTIVE BY MAGDALENA NIESLONY
RICHARD SERRA:
PERSPECTIVITY IN PERSPECTIVE BY MAGDALENA NIESLONY
‘’ Quidquid
recipitur ad modum recipientis recipitur.’’
—Scholastic
Principle
Richard
Serra’s work in general and his more recent sculptures in particular articulate
space in a manner that intends to make the perspectivity of perception
experienceable—but not the perspectivity that, mastered by geometric
construction, has dominated Western seeing and thinking since the early modern
era in the form of central perspective. Serra uses his works to exhibit a
fundamentally different perspectivity that is radically grounded in the body
and makes the contingency of every experience visible. He articulates the experience
of perspectivity in sculptures whose form is perceived in a spatiotemporal
sequence of aspects that cannot possibly be taken in and seen as a gestalt or
synthesized and grasped as a whole in an ordinary perceptual situation.1
In what
follows, I develop a series of reflections on Serra’s interest in the
perspectivity of perception. I show that this interest is rooted in two central
aspects of modern aesthetics: the revalorization of sensuousness as opposed to
rationality and—related to this—the autonomization of art as an originary
sphere of cognition.2 The recognition of Serra’s affinity with these
archetypally modern conceptions prompted me to reexamine the prevailing
Anglo-American view of the sculptor as an exemplary representative of the break
with modernism. He was promoted to this status in the framework of discussions
of postmodernism in art in the circle surrounding the American journal October.
I begin by analyzing recent changes in Serra’s work, since they reveal the relatively traditional character of his artistic position. The qualities of his sculptures that are generally regarded as postmodern—site-specificity and truth to materials (Materialgerechtigkeit)—either play no role at all in the most recent phase of his work or else are of purely secondary importance.
I begin by analyzing recent changes in Serra’s work, since they reveal the relatively traditional character of his artistic position. The qualities of his sculptures that are generally regarded as postmodern—site-specificity and truth to materials (Materialgerechtigkeit)—either play no role at all in the most recent phase of his work or else are of purely secondary importance.
I then go on
to present a lesser known perspective on Serra’s relationship with modernity.
It is a view that deserves more attention, and not just in connection with the
newest developments in his work. In contrast to the October group, a group of
West German art critics surrounding the art historian Max Imdahl regards
Serra’s work of the same period—the late 1970s and 1980s—as a logical
continuation of modern aesthetic questions. In order to show how such a
discrepancy was possible, I explore the premises and arguments of this
specifically German view of Serra, which reach back to the beginnings of modern
aesthetics and theory of art at the end of the eighteenth century.
Finally, I
use the example of Joseph Albers to show the routes by which the
quintessentially modern interest in the complexity of perception was able to
reach postwar American art and find new expression there. For Albers’s basic
artistic principles, which Serra encountered as a student at Yale and which had
a deep and lasting influence on his art, spring from the same sources as the
German critical reception of the sculptor’s work. Thus, my essay deals with two
different instances of conditionality: the historical roots of perspectivity in
Serra’s work and the cultural perspectivity of its interpretation.
1- THE LIGHTNESS OF STEEL
AND THE SPATIAL ANANYMITY OF SCULPTURE
In the
Torqued Ellipses and Torqued Spirals produced beginning in 1996 and the Toruses
and Spheres (fig. 1) that followed them, a change has taken place in Serra’s
artistic language. Two of the principles most fundamental to Serra’s work thus
far—site-specificity and truth to materials—are either completely absent or
only present as secondary aspects.
Let us first
consider what has happened to the principle of site-specificity, that is, how
the sculptures’ relationship with their environment has changed. In
site-specific sculptures, the size, form, and placement of the work or its
elements were ideally prescribed by the site and served to make its structure
visible. “I think you read the site via the sculpture,” says Serra of St.
John’s Rotary Arc.3 And also: “Most of my work (drawings and sculptures) is
site-related. The site determines how I think about what I am going to do,
whether it be an urban or landscape site, a room, or other architectural
enclosure. All the site defining information that’s available is gathered. . .”4
Almost
totally self-contained, the new series of Ellipses and Spirals completely
dispense with any specific connection to their site—with their centered forms,
they are largely hermetic. They set themselves off self-sufficiently from the
scenery around them. This visual impression reflects the fact that they were not
conceived for any particular site. This autonomization of sculpture with
respect to its site already begins to emerge in some of the Arcs of the 1980s,
which, however, almost inevitably enter into a dialogue with their immediate
surroundings as a result of their spatial orientation. This quality is often
taken into account when the works are installed, so that it can sometimes seem
as if they were actually designed for their ultimate location.
Serra
confirms, however, that “[n]one of the coneshapes were built for particular
sites; the ellipses are a continuation of that series. That’s how I got
involved with the problem of a vessel that would entirely surround a volume.
Neither the cones nor the ellipses are dependent on their place. They are not
site-specific pieces. Nor do they need be.”5 And even when he describes what he
considers to be an appropriate site for the ellipses,6 that should not be
confused with his earlier concept of sitespecificity. In Serra’s more recent
works, the environment only plays a role for the artist insofar as it is called
upon to support the visibility of the sculptural form.
The Ellipses
and Spirals also exhibit a changed relationship of form and material compared
to the earlier works. While that relationship, unlike the site, still plays an
important role, the principle of truth to materials has undergone a critical
modification. This principle was first defined as an ideal for architecture and
the production of useful objects by the Arts and Crafts movement and only then
adopted by the fine arts. In the broadest sense, working in a way that is true
to one’s materials means that form should follow material. Essential
consequences of this approach are that the material’s native character should
be revealed and become aesthetically effective, and that alterations to the
material should be kept to a minimum. In contrast to this strict interpretation
of the principle of truth to materials, in Serra’s recent works it is no longer
the resistance, unwieldiness, and above all the cumbersome weight—as it were,
the self-will—of steel that are made visible by the work, as was still the case
with the balanced or tilted slabs with their rough, unfinished surfaces that
deliberately show the traces of their industrial production. Instead, the characteristics
that come to light in the newer works are those that make steel such a
versatile and adaptable material for the construction industry and technology,
including, for example, the fact that it is relatively malleable but rigid in
its final state. The frozen elasticity of the elliptical walls, which sometimes
approach and then recede from the observer, can even produce an impression of
dancelike, animated lightness.7 What is important is that in this new
interpretation, the treatment of the material no longer reflects the ideal that
form should follow material. On the contrary, here that principle is
subordinated to the realization of a formal idea initially conceived
independently of the material aspect of its execution. Thus, the artist sometimes
uses oil to make the color variations between the individual components of the
ellipses and the traces of their handling less visible so as not to disturb the
novel form of spatial perception the sculptures seek to provoke.8 And yet it is
one of the most fundamental axioms of truth to materials that alterations of
the material should be kept to a minimum. Apparently, in his more recent works,
Serra’s primary interest has shifted from the material to the form, which
dictates the choice of the material as well as its treatment. This shift in the
relationship of form and material is thus analogous to that in the relationship
of form and environment: The determining factor becomes the one determined and
vice versa.9
2- EXEMPLARY POSTMODERNIST –
EXEMPLARY MODERN
Serra’s
abandonment of site-specificity and the change in his treatment of material are
so noteworthy because these characteristics, which clearly contradicted the
modernist ideal defined by Clement Greenberg, were the very ones that justified
his reputation as a postmodernist. In Greenberg’s modernism—one of the most
influential “grand narratives” of the development of modern art—the only kind
of sculpture that is progressive and therefore contemporary is sculpture that
emphasizes purely visual qualities and thus in principle approaches the status
of painting. A modernist sculpture seems weightless, almost immaterial, and it
is often intended to be seen from a single perspective. The desired convergence
with painting is achieved not only by means of this mimicry of
two-dimensionality but also through the use of paint, which covers and conceals
the actual material of sculpture. In this way, despite the fact that it
occupies the same space as the observer, sculpture remains autonomous vis-à-vis
the world of everyday life and experience that surrounds it (the world of
non-art and design): It does not cross the aesthetic boundary.10
Thus,
site-specificity and crude materiality are the qualities of Serra’s works that
understandably made them such a success with the American art critics who, in
the 1970s, were starting to rebel against the dominance of Greenberg’s doctrine
and to proclaim that a new era was at hand. Particularly authors associated
with the journal October, such as Krauss, Douglas Crimp, and Hal Foster,
regarded the sculptor as one of the most important protagonists in the
replacement of modernism by postmodernism.11
Through
site-specificity and truth to materials, Serra’s earlier sculptures consciously
and rigorously accentuate their palpable presence within the observer’s spatial
and temporal situation. As we can now see, the more recent phase of Richard
Serra’s work, with its focus on formal questions, clearly emphasizes a certain
autonomy of sculpture and its reception. Serra himself confirms that this
impression is intentional: “As the pieces become more complex, so too does the
temporality they create. It’s not time on the clock, not literal time; it’s
subliminal, it’s subjective, and it differentiates the experience of the
sculptures from daily experience.”12 With the primacy of form over the material
aspects of sculpture and with the autonomization of aesthetic experience,
Serra’s work— despite undeniable differences—begins to approach Greenberg’s
conception of modernist sculpture.13
The recent
formal change in Serra’s work has not gone unnoticed by American critics.
Curiously, however, they never mention Serra’s abandonment of sitespecificity
and truth to materials, the very qualities for which they have thus far admired
him. As if to protect the artist from the accusation of traditionalism, they
focus exclusively on the continuity between this new phase and the more
rebellious ones that preceded it. They often see the principle of that
continuity in the “incommensurability between knowledge, particularly the type
of eidetic knowledge that is the stuff of geometry, and perception,” to quote
Yve-Alain Bois.14 In Foster’s essay on the Torques and Toruses, the emphasis on
continuity clearly serves to allow the author to go on interpreting Serra’s
work as a break with the modernist tradition, even if the term “postmodernism”
is no longer used. Characteristically, Foster maintains that Minimalist
art—among whose representatives he seems to number Serra—has nothing to do with
modernist purity, even if it may seem to at first glance: “Minimalists deployed
pure forms . . . in order to show how they are transformed by our impure
perception, complicated as it always is by embodiment, placement, and
context.”15 Foster evaluates the visual complexity of Serra’s works as an
unambiguously positive feature that differentiates it from European modernist
purity, which is seen as unambiguously negative. However, this simplifying
dichotomy ignores the fact that precisely the discrepancy between perception
and knowledge is a topical motif of certain strands of modern aesthetic
reflection and artistic production. But the topos of the disparateness of
sensuousness and rationality—or art and science—has no place in Greenberg’s
modernism. Foster’s tacit appeal to a two-period model is characteristic of the
profound extent to which Greenberg’s construction of aesthetic modernity as
modernism has shaped American criticism. By contrast, I will argue that while
Serra’s work may be understood as antimodernist and even postmodernist with
respect to Greenberg’s modernism, it should not be seen as postmodern in the
sense of marking an (epochal) break with European modernity as a whole.16
The attempt to situate
Serra within a broader concept of modernity was undertaken in West Germany as
early as the late 1970s by the art historian Max Imdahl,17 whose interpretive
model shaped the perception of Serra in the German-speaking world until the
late 1980s. This shows that where Greenberg’s conception of art was not widely
received and hence did not possess the authority to shape opinions, it was
eminently possible to view Richard Serra’s works as a reinterpretation of
existing artistic questions. Imdahl views Serra from the partisan perspective
of a champion of nonobjective art, in particular the form of nonobjectivity
that Theo van Doesburg described in 1930 as concrete art. Imdahl cites
Doesburg’s distinction between abstract and concrete in several of his essays:
‘ We speak of
concrete and not abstract painting because nothing is more concrete, more real
than a line, a colour, a surface.
A woman, a
tree, a cow: are these concrete elements in painting? No. A woman, a tree and a
cow are concrete only in nature; in painting they are abstract, illusionistic,
vague and speculative.18
According to
Doesburg, unlike merely abstract art, which continues to draw on structures of
visible reality, concrete art creates an autonomous reality entirely free of
any attachment to an extrapictorial reality. Thus, while the former has a
reference point outside itself, the latter is purely self-referential and uses
line, color, and plane without any objective association whatsoever, as
autonomous artistic means. Imdahl, however, clearly is not interested in a
further aspect of concrete art that Doesburg describes in the same manifesto,
an aspect that would go on to have an enormous influence on the appearance of
concrete art in postwar Europe. According to this guideline, concrete art
should develop a universal language on the basis of mathematics as a universal
science.
Against this backdrop, it seems astonishing at first that
Richard Serra’s works, which avoid all logical or mathematical transparency,
should have come to be seen in Germany as the embodiment of concrete art. Thus,
in a conversation with Imdahl, Michael Fehr cites the American sculptor’s works
as a contemporary example of concrete art.19 This classification has its
origins in Imdahl’s essay on “Serra’s Right Angle Prop and Tot: Concrete Art
and Paradigm,” which appeared in the catalogue of the artist’s first large
exhibition in Germany.20 That exhibition took place in 1978, one year after the
sculpture Terminal was prestigiously displayed at Documenta 6 in front of the
Fridericianum and the same year that it was installed in Bochum, where it caused
a sensation and drew protests from the populace.21 The circumstances of the
show were no doubt partially responsible for the fact that Imdahl’s essay met
with the lively interest and that the interpretation presented in it soon
became widely known.
But how was Imdahl able to depict Serra’s work, which was so
different from geometric nonobjectivity à la Doesburg, as an example of
concrete art? The argumentative trick was that he only took the first half of
Doesburg’s definition—the self-referentiality of concrete art—seriously. Imdahl
criticizes the fact that Doesburg’s call for a mathematically structured art
is, as he sees it, essentially in conflict with his first call for pure
selfreferentiality. Mathematically structured form remains in a certain sense referential
and illusionistic, in that in place of material “subjects” it delivers ideal
ones, which are not the quasi-tautological result of the medial character of
the painting or sculpture. The result is that the artwork does not take the
material sufficiently into account but subordinates it to the ideal subject.22
By contrast, Serra’s sculptures are consummate examples of a more radical form
of concrete art:
in that they
possess immediate evidence independent of all phenomenal or imaginative
correlatives outside themselves. . . . Serra’s sculptures Right Angle Prop and
Tot are works of concrete art of a distinctive and radical kind: in them, the
“per se” of concrete art which is for the work to exist by itself and to need
no other explanation is radicalized into self-evidence not only of the form
but also of the material. The material cannot be substituted.23
In Serra’s
Right Angle Prop (fig. 2), Imdahl sees the self-evidence and nonsubstitutable
character of the material realized in the fact that the characteristics of the
material—lead, its heaviness and simultaneous softness and relative
flexibility—are deliberately exposed. This means that a form is not “imposed
on” the material; instead, the latter “actively” participates in the production
of its own form. The characteristics of the material are also thematized in the
sculpture Tot (fig. 3). In this work, Serra employs a semifinished steel panel
with a rectangular cross section that would normally be further transformed in
the process of industrial production. It is lightly embedded in the ground and
therefore cannot be seen in its entirety. The viewer, however, is able to infer
that it is rectangular from the right angles at the top:
[T]he
heaviness of steel becomes apparent as the rectangular form stands inclined.
And the rigidity of steel as a material is exposed as the form is, in spite of
its inclined position, still rectangular or may at least be perceived as a
rectangle.24
What Imdahl
describes here as the consummation of concrete art is none other than the
principle of truth to materials that I discussed at the beginning of this
essay, which is rolled back in Serra’s more recent work and constitutes one of
the genuine elements of the mediaspecific self-reflection of the arts.
3- ART AS
COGNITION
Imdahl interprets the concept of concrete art very broadly.
He includes in it both the geometric and expressive tendencies of European
nonobjectivity as well as a few positions of postwar American art.25 This
enables him to view concrete art as a defining trend of the development of art
in the twentieth century, which then permits him to devote his attention almost
exclusively to it. However, Imdahl’s all-embracing notion of concrete art does
not fully explain why he largely ignores the other artistic positions of
modernity—expressionism, Dadaism, conceptual art, and so on. The reason he
attributes such enormous significance to concrete art in general and to Serra’s
work in particular is that they refrain from representing “previous knowledge”
and therefore make it possible to demonstrate the specific capabilities of the
visual communication of meaning. For in claiming to communicate meaning, the
concrete artwork demonstrates that meaning is located in the sensuous rather
than the conceptual. It is precisely this paradoxical nexus of the
self-reflexive sensuous presence of the work and its capacity for
self-transcendence that constitutes the special value of the concrete artwork.
Imdahl regards a number of Serra’s sculptures as exemplary realizations of this
paradoxical nexus. For example, he admires Right Angle Prop more than the much
better known One Ton Prop / House of Cards, because the latter can be described
with a lexical term that is given in advance—precisely as a “house of cards.”26
He writes: “In so far, however, as a ‘house of cards’ is denoted, the structure
of a sculpture threatens to be (mis)apprehended as the mere variant of an
object already defined by a definite term: the structure of the sculpture is in
danger of no longer being discovered but merely recovered. . .”27 It is easy to
recognize the kinship between Imdahl’s interpretation and what has lately
become the favorite motif of Serra scholarship, the previously mentioned “incommensurability
between knowledge . . . and perception.”28 For Imdahl, however, the
“deconceptualization” of art not only constitutes a feature of Serra’s work but
the most important hallmark of modernity itself.29 Thus, Serra’s contribution
to this tendency—just like the self-evidence of his materials—shows him to be a
follower of the tradition of modernity and even, in a certain sense, one who
carries that tradition to completion. What distinguishes Imdahl’s
interpretation from those of Bois and Foster, however, is his almost
metaphysical semanticizing of the nonobjective works. For him,
deconceptualization does not mean the renunciation of knowledge—on the
contrary, it means the introduction of another, no longer rational or logical
form of cognition, as Imdahl explains in his interpretation of Right Angle Prop:
Stability and
durability of the sculpture appear as nondeformation midst a potential of
deformation. In so far, however, as stability and durability are thematic under
the horizon of deformation and deformation is thematic under the horizon of
stability and durability, a basic structure of existence is present which
becomes the subject of reflection through the sculpture, i.e., through the
material disposition of lead, without thereby suppressing the factual presence
of the sculpture as such. . . . What really is of interest in Serra’s sculpture
Right Angle Prop is not only the material disposition of lead but also a
structure which has its paradigm in the material disposition of lead.30
Imdahl uses
his central notion of the “paradigm” to describe the special way that concrete
artworks relate to their meaning. They differ from copying, mimetic
representations in that they exemplify their signified selves—they themselves
are models or paradigms of it: “Serra’s sculpture is not the image but a real
instance of an existential structure.”31
This kind of semantic potentiation of the artwork
presupposes a belief that the work possesses a level of meaning that goes
beyond what is factually present and aims at universal structures of human
existence. Art’s communication of meaning remains essentially irreplaceable and
untranslatable. As Imdahl says himself, this belief may be regarded as the
foundation of the hermeneutic conception of art:
It is a
fundamental content of the visual arts . . . not just to formulate the
otherwise unavailable ideal but also to provide concrete data for intuition
[Anschauungsgegebenheiten]— accessible and comprehensible to sense
perception—of what is otherwise unimaginable and indemonstrable, indeed simply
to draw attention to what is otherwise unimaginable and indemonstrable. It
would be easy to see the artwork as legitimated precisely by its ability to
bring structures to light—to make them an experience for intuition [Anschauung]
and an object of reflection—that are otherwise closed to us and ignored, indeed
perhaps even unconceived of.32
However,
Imdahl remains consistent with the notion that art is irreplaceable—the
aesthetic experience33 made possible by art cannot be replaced by the
experience of nature or other realms of everyday life. Art alone makes the
“unimaginable,” the “indemonstrable,” and even—as he writes on another
occasion—the otherwise “invisible” visible.34 At the same time, the autonomy of
art, which for Imdahl lies primarily in the uniqueness of its cognitive
potential, is defined as mediated rather than absolute; for a hermeneutician
the umbilical cord between art and life remains uncut.
Just as the American interpretation of Serra is partially
determined by its intellectual context— Greenberg’s modernism and the emerging
theories of postmodernity—so Imdahl also draws on other theoretical positions.
For example, the claim that art is a form of cognition betrays the direct
influence of Hans-Georg Gadamer’s hermeneutics. Thus, the first part of
Gadamer’s major work, Truth and Method, is devoted to the “question of truth as
it emerges in the experience of art.” Art is depicted there as the exemplary
sphere that allows one to distinguish the hermeneutic comprehension of the
world from the methodical explanation characteristic of the natural sciences.35
Gadamer espouses a moderate epistemological constructivism—for him, the artwork
is not a purely mimetic representation of the world but a necessarily biased
interpretation of it. According to this view, the function of a picture (Bild)
is not merely to refer to an original (Ur-Bild)—what is important is precisely
how it shows what it represents. The original undergoes an “increase in
being”36 in the picture, in that the picture says something about its model
that would not exist in precisely that way in the absence of the pictorial
representation: “[N]on-differentiation of presentation and what is represented”
remains an essential characteristic of all pictorial experience. At this
juncture, Gadamer speaks of the “irreplaceability of the picture,” a conception
that, as we have seen, also plays a central role for Imdahl.37
However, it would be a mistake to view Imdahl’s notion of
art as exclusively derived from Gadamer’s position.38 The genealogy of Imdahl’s
art-theoretical convictions reaches back to German Idealism, which especially
affects the semantic plane of many of his interpretations of individual works.
The notion of the paradigm, which Imdahl employs in his discussions of Serra’s
works, bears an unmistakable resemblance to the notion of the symbol as
developed by Goethe and Karl Philipp Moritz and expanded into a universal
aesthetic principle by Idealist philosophy.39 In the aesthetics of German
Idealism, the symbol must fulfill two requirements: clarity and a
representative meaning, that is, the delegation and making present of something
universal by a particular existent that is an eminent and characteristic part
of that universal. A particular thing of this kind can make the universal
present.40 In this understanding of the symbol, it is essential that the latter
have a dual character, because it is both itself—a specific and inherently
meaningful individual thing—as well as the objectification of an abstract universal
principle.41 Imdahl has this same dual character in view when, writing of
Serra’s sculptures, he observes both the work’s “self-evidence” and “a meaning
which transcends such mere self-containedness,” a meaning that is “present” in
the work.42
If Imdahl avoids the word
“symbol,” that may be because it was strongly criticized precisely by
Gadamer.43 However, this does nothing to alter the fact that Imdahl assigns a
cognitive importance to art that is otherwise only attributed to philosophy.
This too is a legacy of Idealist aesthetics, as formulated, for example, by
Friedrich Wilhelm von Schelling.44 For the aestheticians of Weimar classicism
and Idealism as well as for Imdahl, the intimate unity of ideal and appearance
implies the irreplaceability of the artwork, since a linguistic rendering of
the artwork can only ever yield an approximation of its content. Thus, for
Goethe, “a true work of art . . . always [has] something of infinity in it to
our minds, as well as a work of nature. We contemplate it, we perceive and
relish its beauties, it makes an impression, but it cannot be thoroughly
understood, nor its essence nor its merit be clearly defined by words.”45
Of course, the artworks referred to by Goethe and subsequent
theories of the symbol bear little if any resemblance to the works of concrete
art. Moreover, in the nineteenth century the notion of the symbol acquired a
definitional subtlety that is missing from Imdahl’s notion. For him too,
however, it remains the case that the perception of art stands in the service
of something higher that can only be attained through intuition (Anschauung).46
In fact, this “elevating” concept of intuition is already outmoded when Imdahl
presents his conception of art. It was constitutive for aesthetics until the
advent of the structuralist theory of meaning, at which point it was replaced
by a “sober” notion of intuition. For in structuralism’s view, the visual sign
does not lead to a higher and otherwise inaccessible realm but translates
something of equal value from another “language.” While the translation can
never replace the original medium and thus in no way negates the basic
disparity of media, it does not lead to a higher valuation of one medium or the
other.47 The almost metaphysical inflation of the cognitive potential of art is
a weakness of Imdahl’s approach, which is epistemologically anachronistic.48
Imdahl’s semanticization of Serra’s works is also an important difference
between his interpretations and those of American critics.
4- ART VERSUS SCIENCE
Imdahl argues
for Serra’s modernity by pointing out the affinity between the artistic
problems that interest him and principles of modern aesthetics and theory of
art. But are there concrete historical indications that Serra’s interest in the
complexity of perception and in material is more than a merely parallel
position? This question may be answered in the affirmative if we consider
Serra’s connection with Josef Albers. When Serra first came to Yale, the former
Bauhaus teacher had just retired. However, Serra studied Albers’s theory of
color when he taught his class on color in his final year. Afterward, Albers
invited him to work on the publication of his textbook on the Interaction of
Color. 49 Nevertheless, a comparison of Serra with the former Bauhaus teacher
and champion of a European “geometric” painting that was strongly criticized by
some in the United States may at first seem strange. The initial surprise
disappears, however, when we leave aside the generic and formal differences
between the artworks and instead consider the artists’ intellectual premises,
their conceptions of the mission of art and of the meaning of visual perception
and its reformulation in art.
Albers saw it as the aim of his pedagogical work to open his
students’ eyes, and similarly he saw the aim of art as the “revelation and
evocation of vision.”50 However, both his didactic and his artistic efforts
have often been misunderstood as geometric, cold, and devoid of sensuality. In
actual fact, the opposite is the case: For Albers, as for Serra, simple
geometric forms and working in series are not ends in themselves but serve
precisely to draw the viewer’s attention to the unsystematizable sensation of
seeing. Serra recalls Albers’s central importance to his own conception of
material and process:
What I
admired about Albers was that even though his format was strict and logical,
within it there was room for play. His color course was not taught
dogmatically—. . . the range of experiments helped you to understand that you could
use material in such a way that it would inform whatever you were making. . . .
And once you understood the basic lesson that procedure was dictated by
material, you also realized that matter imposed its own form on form. That’s a
lesson I never forgot.51
Albers himself writes of color:
Color, when
practically applied, not only appears in uncountable shades and tints, but is
additionally characterized by shape and size, by recurrence and placement, and
so on. . . . All this may signify why any color composition naturally defies
such diagrammatic registration as notation in music and choreography in dance.52
For Albers,
perception in general and color perception in particular are relative, change
over time, and cannot be fixed in systems. Perception delivers “actual facts,”
by contrast with the objective, measurable, and constant knowledge of science,
which Albers calls “factual facts.” This binary opposition reflects the most
important basis of Albers’s conception of art, the discrepancy between physical
facts and “psychical” effects.53 Or as he expresses it figuratively elsewhere:
“In the sciences 1 + 1 is always 2—in art it can also be 3.”54 Precisely in the
use of the mathematical metaphor, it is easy to recognize the modern topos of
art’s alogical character, as formulated even more pointedly by the Russian Ivan
Puni in 1915: “2 x 2 is whatever you like, just not four.”55 Not only Josef
Albers but also a substantial number of artists of the early twentieth century
defined themselves in conscious opposition to the realm of logic and
rationality, recasting the alogical character of their own sphere as an
advantage:
The object
has no absolute form. It can have various forms. They do not coincide with the
geometric form. Geometry is science, painting—art. The former is absolute and
the second necessarily relative. If it contradicts logic, so much the worse
(for logic).56
What is here
asserted of painting determines Serra’s conception of art from the very
beginning of his career. He writes in one of his earliest texts, recalling
Albers and other modern precursors:
The
perception of the work . . . does not give one calculable truth like geometry,
but a sense of presence, an isolated time. The apparent potential for disorder,
for movement endows the structure with a quality outside of its physical or
relational definition.57
He even goes
on to support this formulation with quotations:
“We
experience more than we can analyse” (A. N. Whitehead). “Sensibility is
inclusive and precedes analytic awareness” (Anonymous). In San Francisco they
say, “Flash on it.”58
In the years
that follow, Serra seeks to do justice to his “plea for perceptual wholeness”59
on various levels. He refuses to design his works before producing them, allows
the material to play a constitutive role in the production of his forms, and
incorporates the site into the genesis of the work. Finally, he designs formal
constellations that reveal the radical perspectivity of perception. He chooses
the unsystematizable character of seeing as his primary field of investigation
and seeks with his work to make the viewer conscious of the complexity of
perceptual data and processes, which is overlooked in everyday life. It is
almost a necessary consequence of this attitude that seeing is slowed down and
made more difficult.60 In this context, site-specificity and truth to
materials—the dominant qualities in Serra’s earlier work—and the radical
perspectivity of the current phase, which began in 1996 with the Torqued
Ellipses, are revealed to be different original solutions to the task of
investigating perception in all its complexity. If the renunciation of the
earlier strategies signals a prominent break in Serra’s oeuvre, that only makes
all the clearer his constant, unwavering reference to the modern aesthetics of
autonomy, whose chief concern was to establish aesthetics as a sphere of
cognition with its own independent laws.
As I have shown, the discrepancy between perception and
concept is also recognized by American critics as a fundamental aspect of
Serra’s work. But while here—under the influence of Greenberg’s concept of
modernism—Serra’s “impure perception” is interpreted as a break with modernism,
from the German perspective the very same quality may be regarded as a high
point in the development of modern art. This diametrically opposed assessment
is based on a conception of art that is rooted in German Idealism and philosophical
hermeneutics. In this conception, art differentiates itself from science and
logic, focuses on its own sensuous cognitive possibilities, and confidently
defines itself as an independent and autonomous sphere of cognition.
In postwar American art, the “declaration of independence”
from the generation of the European fathers plays an important role,61 and
“patricide” is very much regarded as a virtuous act, even if the artists’
selfperception is primarily wishful thinking. For precisely the example of Serra’s
current development points to a line connecting postwar American art to the
aesthetic ideas of the older generation of European artists, as I have
demonstrated with the example of Josef Albers. However, in addition to the
rejection of modernism, the anti-European rhetoric is probably also partially
responsible for the fact that the connections are hardly ever thematized in
Anglo-American criticism. The constant theme of Serra’s entire oeuvre, which
comes to light all the more powerfully in his more recent, radically
perspectival and yet in a certain sense more traditional works—the discrepancy
between perception and concept—represents an almost topical line of this kind
connecting modern artistic theory and practice on either side of the Atlantic.
—Translated from the
German by James Gussen
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
I wish to
thank Joseph Leo Koerner for his guidance and support in the writing of this
essay.
1- The importance of the
perspectivity of perception for Serra’s conception of sculpture is thematized
by several of his interpreters. These interpreters tend to point to the kinship
of Serra’s position with that of Maurice Merleau-Ponty, as presented in the
latter’s Phenomenology of Perception. Characteristically, Rosalind E. Krauss
places the following quotation from Merleau-Ponty at the beginning of her essay
on Serra: “But the system of experience is not arrayed before me as if I were
God, it is lived by me from a certain point of view; I am not the spectator, I
am involved, and it is my involvement in a point of view which makes possible
both the finiteness of my perception and its opening out upon the complete
world as a horizon of every perception.” See R. Krauss, “Richard Serra, a
Translation,” in The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths
(Cambridge, Mass. and London: The MIT Press, 1985), p. 261. Other examples of a
“phenomenological” interpretation of Serra’s work include: D. Craven, “Richard
Serra and the Phenomenology of Perception,” Arts Magazine 60, no. 7 (March
1986) and N. P. Griffith, “Richard Serra and Robert Irwin: Phenomenology in the
Age of Art and Objecthood” (Ph.D. diss., The University of Michigan, 1993). The
“phenomenological” interpretation emphasizes Serra’s rejection of the “Gestalt
reading” of the form of his sculptures.
2- Serra’s embrace of the
notion of a (relative) autonomy of art with respect to other spheres of social
reality and practice is touched on in passing by Stephen Melville in his 2004
essay for RES: “Richard Serra: Thinking the Measure of the Impossible,” RES 46
(Autumn 2004):188.
3- R. Serra, “Richard
Serra’s Urban Sculpture,” interview by Douglas Crimp (1980), in Richard Serra,
Writings/Interviews (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994), p. 136.
4- R. Serra, interview by
Bernard Lamarche-Vadel (1980), in Serra (ibid.), p. 115.
5- R. Serra, interview by
David Sylvester in Richard Serra: Sculpture 1985–1998, ed. Russell Ferguson,
Anthony McCall, and Clara Weyergraf-Serra (Los Angeles: The Museum of
Contemporary Art, 1999), p. 194.
6- “I am interested in an
external architectural referent; the outside of the form reads better, its
definition is clearer, in relation to a vertical plane than it would be in
relation to a flat open landscape.” R. Serra, interview by Lynne Cooke and
Michael Govan, Richard Serra: Torqued Ellipses (New York: Dia Center for the
Arts, 1997), p. 16.
7- When asked by David
Sylvester if he “would agree that the ellipses seem to be in perpetual
movement,” Serra gives an apt description of the impression they produce: “I
think they implicate you in their movement. They have a torque, and when you
walk into them, in order to understand their torque, you move, and as you move
they move, so you’re always trying to play catch-up with them.” Richard Serra:
Sculpture 1985–1998 (see note 5), p. 203.
8- With regard to the
surface treatment of one of his ellipses, Serra tells David Sylvester: “I did
something there that I’m usually very reluctant to do. The crew at Beth Ship
had great difficulties bending these pieces precisely, especially the one where
the top ellipse is at a right angle to the bottom ellipse. That piece had to be
line-heated to bring it together. . . . The scars on the piece were so bad that
they interfered with the reading of the internal spin. We didn’t have a choice,
I had to sandblast the whole surface inside and out. But even after
sandblasting and after the plates had been outside and weathered and rusted,
the line-heating marks were still visible. I needed to erase the scars so that
you read the torque, that’s why we decided to oil this piece. As I said, I have
been reluctant to do that in most of my pieces, but here it was a trade-off. .
. . I don’t like to obliterate the process that goes into the work, but if the
manufacture interferes with the perception and putting oil on the piece can
correct the problem, I thought, why not.” Richard Serra: Sculpture 1985–1998
(see note 5), p. 201.
9- Thus, the material still
plays an important role for Serra. He has reflected on the choice of materials
on a number of occasions, for example, in an interview by Lynne Cooke and
Michael Govan: “When I thought I was not going to be able to make these pieces
in steel, several architects advised me to build them in concrete. But the
problem with making them in concrete . . . would have been that they would be
compared to architecture. I wanted to keep them within the definition of
sculpture, I did not want to start begging issues that seem irrelevant to
sculpture. . . . Also, built in concrete, these pieces would totally lose the
tension of the torqued steel, which affects your experience of their space.”
And also: “I’m using steel now almost like you would use rubber, in a very
elastic way. . . . We made lead models of the elliptical pieces, because lead
is malleable, and once we could make smallscale lead models with the wheel, we
figured it might be possible with a dense enough roller with great compression
to make them in steel. If there was another material that I thought would give
me the same compression and torquing of space, I would have no reason not to
use it.” Richard Serra: Torqued Ellipses (see note 6), pp. 17 and 22ff.
Though Serra
admits that the hierarchy of his concerns and his concept of how to handle
steel have changed, he would probably disagree with my view that his new
approach to material is fundamentally distinct from his former practice: “The
articulation of space has come to take precedence over other concerns. . . . I
want to emphasize that I am not interested in form as pure abstraction. I am interested
in form as a conjunction between space and matter. Matter, any material
whatsoever, imposes its own form on form. To me Louis Kahn’s brick is still
relevant.” R. Serra, “Questions, Contradictions, Solutions: Early Work,” in
Richard Serra: The Matter of Time (Bilbao: Guggenheim Museum, 2005), p. 54.
10- C. Greenberg, “The
New Sculpture,” Partisan Review 16 (June 1949):637–642; also by him: “Sculpture
in Our Time,” Arts Magazine 32, no. 10 (June 1958):22–25; “Recentness of
Sculpture,” in American Sculpture of the Sixties (Los Angeles: Los Angeles
County Museum of Art, 1967).
11- See for example: R.
Krauss, “Sculpture in the Expanded Field,” October, no. 8 (1979): 31–44;
Krauss, “Richard Serra: Sculpture,” in Richard Serra: Sculpture (New York: Museum
of Modern Art, 1986); D. Crimp, “Richard Serra: Sculpture Exceeded,” October,
no. 18 (1981):67–78; Crimp, “Redefining Site Specificity,” in Richard Serra:
Sculpture (New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1986); H. Foster, “The Crux of
Minimalism,” in Individuals: A Selected History of Contemporary Art 1945–1986,
ed. Howard Singerman (New York: Abbeville Press, 1986).
12- R. Serra, “On ‘The
Matter of Time,’” interview by Hal Foster, Artforum 44, no. 1 (Sept. 2005):271.
13- “Being relaxed
about the very principles on which his art is grounded . . . allowed Serra to
think about the process of engendering sculptural forms in ways he would likely
have condemned before. Indeed the purely geometrical issue he began with . . .
may explain why, for once, the rhetoric of weight that has always
(unnecessarily) encumbered the appreciation of his work is irrelevant. ‘Each
sculpture [weighs] forty tons, yet they don’t seem heavy. . . . There’s a
certain weightlessness to them,’ he says, and the plates ‘could be thinner.’
How unusual of Serra, and how remarkably unself-conscious, to be able to speak
that way. It almost sounds like Greenberg’s old notion of sculpture as optical
mirage, something that Serra, among others, has always rejected, and for good
reason.” Y.-A. Bois, “Richard Serra. Dia Center for the Arts,” Artforum 36, no.
5 (January 1998):97. Though I agree with Bois’s keen observation, I am not
convinced by his marginalization of the role of weight in Serra’s earlier
works. This seems to be a subsequent projection. Serra consistently emphasizes
the importance of weight for his sculptural work: “Weight is a value for me,
not that it is any more compelling than lightness, but I simply know more about
weight than lightness and therefore I have more to say about it. . .” R. Serra,
“Weight” [1988], in Serra (note 3), p. 184.
14- Bois (ibid.), p. 97.
15- H. Foster, “Torques and
Toruses,” in Richard Serra: Torqued Spirals, Toruses and Spheres (New York:
Gagosian Gallery, 2001), p. 7.
16- My view shares certain
points in common with other lines of argument. For example, in an earlier text
Bois develops a parallel between Serra’s interest in the temporality and
multiplicity of visual experience and the idea of the picturesque garden in the
eighteenth century (see Y.-A. Bois, “Promenade pittoresque autour de
Clara-Clara,” in Richard Serra [Paris: Musée National d’Art Moderne, Centre
Georges Pompidou, 1983] and, also by him, “A Picturesque Stroll around
ClaraClara,” in Richard Serra, ed. H. Foster and G. Hughes [Cambridge, Mass.:
The MIT Press, 2000]). Bois favors a conception in which modernity begins in
the eighteenth century. He argues explicitly against a narrow construction of
the modern as modernism and implicitly against the interpretation of Serra’s
works as postmodern. David Clarke’s position is even closer to my own. He sees
Serra’s “practice . . . as a renewal of the [pre-formalist] modernist project”
by means of “a recomplexification of art.” D. Clarke, “The Gaze and the Glance:
Competing Understandings of Visuality in the Theory and Practice of Late
Modernist Art,” Art History 15, no. 1 (March 1992):93.
17- Max Imdahl (1925–1988)
was a polarizing figure in West German art history. His opponents found fault
with his methodological approach, which he termed “Ikonik” in a critical
reference to Panofsky’s Iconology. By contrast with Panofsky’s text-oriented
approach to interpretation, Ikonik deals with how meaning is produced by the
inherent qualities of the image. Because of his lack of interest in a
contextual (historical, social, etc.) analysis, Imdahl was accused of
formalism. Imdahl’s Ikonik and other related positions came to be known as
“art-historical hermeneutics” (kunsthistorische Hermeneutik). This makes clear
their connection with the philosophical hermeneutics of Hans-Georg Gadamer,
which is discussed below.
18- M. Imdahl, Gesammelte
Schriften (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1996), vol. 1, p. 131; vol. 3, pp. 238,
383, 418ff. The quotation comes from Doesburg’s “Comments on the Basis of
Concrete Painting” [1930], quoted here from the English translation in J.
Baljeu, Theo van Doesburg (London: Studio Vista; New York: Macmillan, 1974), p.
181.
19- Imdahl (ibid.), vol. 1,
p. 374.
20- M. Imdahl, “Serra’s Right
Angle Prop und Tot. Konkrete Kunst und Paradigma,” in Richard Serra (Tübingen
and Baden-Baden: Kunsthalle, 1978), translated by S. Kisro-Völker in “Serra’s
Right Angle Prop and Tot: Concrete Art and Paradigm,” ibid.; German version
reprinted in Imdahl (see note 18), vol. 1. Imdahl also deals with Serra’s works
in other texts: “Zu ausgewählten Arbeiten von Jan Meyer-Rogge,” in Stillwasser.
Plastische Arbeiten von Jan Meyer-Rogge (Bochum: Museum Bochum, 1980),
reprinted in Imdahl (note 18), vol. 1 (with an analysis of Right Angle Prop and
Terminal), and “Zur Wiedereröffnung der Kunstsammlungen der Ruhr-Universität
Bochum,” Jahrbuch der Ruhr-Universität Bochum (1982), reprinted as “Richard
Serra, Untitled” in Imdahl (note 18), vol. 1 (on the drawing Untitled).
Examples of
the influence of Imdahl’s interpretation on German discourse include: A. von
Berswordt-Wallrabe, “Gedanken zur Skulptur Gedenkstätte Goslar (1981) und
Äußerungen von Richard Serra,” in Richard Serra (Goslar: Mönchehaus Museum and
Verein zur Förderung Moderner Kunst, 1981); E.-G. Güse, “Fassbinder und die
Existenz des Künstlers,” in Richard Serra (Münster: Westfälisches Landesmuseum
für Kunst und Kulturgeschichte, 1987); R. Hoppe-Sailer, “Druckprozeß. Zu den
graphischen Arbeiten von Richard Serra,” in Richard Serra. Das druckgraphische
Werk 1972–1988 (Berlin: Neuer Berliner Kunstverein, 1988).
21- On the controversy
surrounding the installation of Terminal, see Terminal von Richard
Serra. Eine
Dokumentation in 7 Kapiteln (Bochum: Museum Bochum, 1980).
22- Imdahl, “Serra’s Right
Angle Prop and Tot” (see note 20), p. 22.
23- Ibid.
24- Ibid., p. 221.
25- See Imdahl’s essay “‘Is
It a Flag or Is It a Painting?’ Über mögliche Konsequenzen der konkreten Kunst”
[1969], in Imdahl (note 18), vol. 1, pp. 131–180. Along with Jasper Johns, he
lists Jackson Pollock, Barnett Newman, and Frank Stella as exponents of concrete
24. Ibid., p. 221. painting.
26- This transparency of the
work to a notion it “illustrates,” as it were, may explain the interest of
conceptual artists in One Ton Prop, which Serra himself regarded as a
misunderstanding. See Serra’s statement in an interview by Hal Foster in “On
The Matter of Time” (note 9), p. 28.
27- Imdahl (see note 18),
vol. 1, pp. 321ff.
28- Bois, “Richard Serra”
(see note 13), p. 97. The refusal of Serra’s works to be grasped conceptually,
as a gestalt, is also the focus of the most recent texts. See, for example, L.
Cooke, “Thinking on Your Feet: Richard Serra’s Sculptures in Landscape,” and J.
Rajchman, “Serra’s Abstract Thinking,” both in Richard Serra Sculpture: Forty
Years (New York: Museum of Modern Art, 2007).
29- In his essay “Die Rolle
der Farbe in der neueren französischen Malerei. Abstraktion und Konkretion”
[1966], in Imdahl (note 18, vol. 3), Imdahl outlines a historical development
that begins in the seventeenth century and leads to abstraction and concrete art.
He argues that the increasing concern with color is rooted in a more general
transformation, in which the rationalistic model of cognition is challenged by
visual experience. This process leads to epistemological skepticism and the
decline of metaphysics.
30- Imdahl, “Serra’s Right
Angle Prop and Tot” (note 20), p. 220.
31- Ibid. Imdahl also
interprets the sculpture Tot as the paradigm of an existential structure: the
structure of “negation . . . the ‘no longer’ of basic orientations [that are]
normally valid.” The square form of Tot delineates the horizontal and the
vertical as the basic directions that Imdahl calls the “primary orientation of
our spatial being-in-the-world.” Since the square is only slightly tilted, the
sculpture still evokes its upright position “as the norm which is left [behind]
and negated, as a value [which is] no longer valid. . .” Ibid., p. 221.
32- M. Imdahl, “James
Reineking, Trace (1972/73–1975),” in Imdahl (see note 18), vol. 1, p. 354. Here
Imdahl explicitly formulates this fundamental concept that implicitly governs
his thinking on art in general.
33- On the concept of
ästhetische Erfahrung (aesthetic experience), see G. Maag, “Erfahrung,” in
Ästhetische Grundbegriffe. Historisches Wörterbuch in 7 Bänden, ed. Karlheinz
Barck, Martin Fontius, Dieter Schlenstedt, Burkhart Steinwachs, and Friedrich
Wolfzettel (Stuttgart/ Weimar: Metzler, 2000), vol. 1, pp. 260–275. In the
hermeneutics and reception theory of the 1970s, this multifaceted term was used
to refer to a discrete realm of cognition viewed as distinct from rationality
and logic. See ibid., p. 274, and H. R. Jauss, Kleine Apologie der ästhetischen
Erfahrung. Mit kunstgeschichtlichen Bemerkungen von Max Imdahl, Konstanzer
Universitätsreden 59 (Konstanz: Universitätsverlag, 1972).
34- Imdahl (see note
18), vol. 3, p. 562.
35- H.-G. Gadamer,
Wahrheit und Methode. Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik [1960]
(translated as Truth and Method, by J. Weinsheimer and D. Marshall [New York
and London: Continuum, 2003]). “The question of truth as it emerges in the
experience of art” is the title of the first part of Truth and Method, in which
Gadamer seeks to develop a general philosophical hermeneutics.
36- Ibid., p, 140. On
the notion of the picture, see chapter II.2.a, “The Ontological Valence of the
Picture,” pp. 134–144.
37- Ibid., p. 139 and
Imdahl (see note 18), vol. 3, p. 620.
38- Unlike Gadamer and
the exponents of reception theory, Imdahl does not analyze the historical
conditions within which works of art are perceived.
39- On the notion of
the symbol in the aesthetics of German Idealism, see Gadamer 2003 (note 35),
pp. 70–81; G. Pochat, Der Symbolbegriff in der Ästhetik und Kunstwissenschaft
(Cologne: Dumont, 1983); and J. L. Koerner, Caspar David Friedrich and the Subject
of Landscape (London: Reaktion Books, 1990), pp. 122–142. G. Kurz, Metapher,
Allegorie, Symbol (Göttingen:
40- Vandenhoeck und
Ruprecht, 1982), p. 69.
41- Pochat (see note
39), p. 23.
42- Imdahl, “Serra’s
Right Angle Prop and Tot” (see note 20), p. 220.
43- Gadamer, Truth and
Method (note 35), pp. 70–81.
44- See, for example,
R. Prange, Die Geburt der Kunstgeschichte. Phliosophische Ästhetik und
empirische Wissenschaft (Cologne: Deubner Verlag, 2004), pp. 59–71.
45- J. W. Goethe,
“Über Laokoon” [1798] (anonymously translated as “Observations on the Laocoon,”
in Goethe on Art, ed. J. Gage [Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of
California Press, 1980], p. 78).
46- On the history of
the notion of intuition (Anschauung), see W. Naumann-Beyer, “Anschauung,” in
Ästhetische Grundbegriffe (note 33), vol. 1, pp. 208–246.
47- Naumann-Beyer sees
Gadamer’s hermeneutics and its application to specific fields as the last
remaining niches where the “elevating” concept of intuition still exists today.
Ibid., p. 211.
48- Gadamer explains in
Truth and Method that the symbol differs from allegory precisely in being
endowed by thought with the presence of a meaning, a presence that it is
perfectly legitimate to regard as metaphysical. See Gadamer, Truth and Method
(note 35), p. 73. Imdahl writes that concrete art does not exist in the context
of a metaphysics but is nonetheless “burdened with the prodigious and probably
impossible task of producing from within itself—that is, from
nothing—information with a metaphysical coloring.” Imdahl (see note 18), vol.
1, p. 315.
49- Serra discusses his
connection to Albers in interviews with Hal Foster (in Serra: The Matter of
Time [see note 9]), p. 24) and Kynaston McShine (in Richard Serra Sculpture:
Forty Years [see note 28], pp. 17–18).
50- J. Albers, Search
Versus Re-Search: Three Lectures by Josef Albers at Trinity College, April 1965
(Hartford, Conn.: Trinity College Press, 1969), p. 10.
51- Richard Serra, in
Richard Serra Sculpture: Forty Years (see note 28), p. 18.
52- J. Albers,
Interaction of Color [1963] (New Haven and London: Yale University Press,
2006), pp. 40–41. On the “actual/factual” distinction, see ibid., p. 117.
53- On the discrepancy
between science and art, see Albers (note 50), p. 10: “The Origin of Art: The
Discrepancy between Physical Fact and Psychical Effect.”
54- Josef Albers, cited
in W. Spies, Albers (Stuttgart: Hatje, 1970), p. 5 (no source given). Albers
also thematizes the alogical character of perception in one of his lectures,
entitled “One Plus One Equals Three and More: Factual Facts and Actual Facts”;
see Albers, Search Versus Re-Search (note 50), 17ff.
55- Suprematist
Manifesto, published by Ivan Puni and Xana Boguslavskaia on the occasion of the
“Last Futurist Exhibition of Paintings 0,10” (Moscow 1915), in Jean Pougny.
Catalogue de l’œuvre, ed. H. Berninger and J.-A. Cartier (Tübingen: Wasmuth,
1972), vol. 1, pp. 52, 153–154 (French translation).
56- N. Kulbin,
“Kubizm,” Strelets (1915), pp. 209ff (in Russian, translation by the author).
57- Serra, “Play It
Again, Sam” [1970], reprinted in Serra (see note 3), p. 7.
58- Ibid., p. 8.
59- Ibid., p. 7.
60- “The act of seeing,
and the concentration of seeing, takes an effort. The gardens impose that
effort on you if you want to see them. It’s another way of ordering your
vision, and it slows down your vision. That was helpful to me, very helpful.”
Serra on the role of Japanese gardens in his own work, in an interview by Lynne
Cooke and Michael Govan (see note 6), p. 29.
61- The anti-European
rhetoric of American artists, their denial of any connection with the preceding
generation of European artists, would be worth investigating in its own right.
Barnett Newman is just one prominent example of this attitude in the New York
School. See Y.-A. Bois, “On Two Paintings by Barnett Newman,” October, no. 108
(Spring 2004):3–27. Examples from the minimal art generation include Donald
Judd and Frank Stella, who attempt to distinguish sharply between their
“geometric” art and its European counterpart. See, for example, Frank Stella
and Donald Judd, “Questions to Stella and Judd” [1966], interview by Bruce
Glaser, reprinted in Minimal Art. A Critical Anthology, ed. G. Battcock
(Berkeley, Los Angeles, and London: University of California Press, 1968)
https://jstor.org/stable/25608808?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents
INFINITY
SEQUENCE
SEQUENCE
SNAKE 1994 - 1997
Snake, a work
made for the inauguration of the Guggenheim Museum
Bilbao, consists of three enormous, serpentine ribbons of hot-rolled
steel that are permanently installed in the museum's “Fish” gallery. Although
it weighs around 180 tons, the colossal work is experienced through its
negative spaces. The two tilted, snaking passages, capture a rare sense of
motion and instability. Snake preceded Serra's Torqued Ellipses,
the artist's most recent rumination on the physicality of space and the nature
of sculpture. BothSnake and the Torqued Ellipses seem to
defy gravity and logic, making solid metal appear as malleable as felt.
Shifting in unexpected ways as viewers walk in and around them, these
sculptures create surprising experiences of space and balance, and provoke a
dizzying sensation of steel and space in motion.
SNAKE 1994 - 1997
Weathering Steel
3 Units, Each Comprised of 2 Conical Sections
Dimensions: Each Section: 4 x 15.85 m; Overall: 4 x 31.7 x 7.84 m;
Weathering Steel
3 Units, Each Comprised of 2 Conical Sections
Dimensions: Each Section: 4 x 15.85 m; Overall: 4 x 31.7 x 7.84 m;
Plate Thickness: 5 cm
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
JUNCTION 2011
Weatherproof Steel
Dimensions: 397.5 × 2287.3 × 1518.8 cm
BETWEEN THE TORUS
& THE SPHERE 2003 - 2005
Weathering Steel
4 Torus and 4 Spherical Sections
Dimensions: Each Section: 4.27 x 15.24 m; Overall: 4.27 x 15.24 x 16.44 m;
Weathering Steel
4 Torus and 4 Spherical Sections
Dimensions: Each Section: 4.27 x 15.24 m; Overall: 4.27 x 15.24 x 16.44 m;
Plate Thickness: 5 cm
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
BLIND SPOT REVERSED 2003 - 2005
Weathering Steel
3 Torus & 3 Spherical Sections
Dimensions: Overall: 4 x 17.2 x 9.04 m; Plate Thickness: 5 cm
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
Weathering Steel
3 Torus & 3 Spherical Sections
Dimensions: Overall: 4 x 17.2 x 9.04 m; Plate Thickness: 5 cm
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
DOUBLE TORQUED
ELLIPSE, 2003 - 2004
Weathering Steel
Dimensions: Outer Ellipse: 4.27 x 11.41 x 12.19 m;
Weathering Steel
Dimensions: Outer Ellipse: 4.27 x 11.41 x 12.19 m;
Inner Ellipse: 4.27 x
6.2 x 9.75 m; Plate Thickness: 5 cm
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
© Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa, 2015
CALVINO 2009
Paintstick on Handmade Paper
Dimensions: 199.4 × 199.4 cm
OUT OF ROUND X, 1999 - 2008
Novatone Print, on Heavy
Tintoretto-Gesso Paper
Dimensions: 69.4 × 59.4 cm
Schellmann
Art, Munich & New York
BORGES 2009
Paintstick on Handmade Paper
Dimensions: 199.4 × 199.4 cm
1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8 - 1987
Hot - Rolled Steel, Eight Plates
Dimensions: Each: 184.8 x 400 x 5.1 cm, Collection
of the Artist
© Richard Serra 2011, © FMGBGuggenheim
Bilbao Museoa, 2011
VORTEX 2002
Cor-ten Steel
Dimensions: 67 feet 10 inches x 21 feet 9 inches x 20 feet 10 inches
Dimensions: 67 feet 10 inches x 21 feet 9 inches x 20 feet 10 inches
Gift of the Burnett Foundation in Honor
of Michael Auping
© 2002 Richard Serra
VORTEX 2002
Cor-ten Steel
Dimensions: 67 feet 10 inches x 21 feet 9 inches x 20 feet 10 inches
Dimensions: 67 feet 10 inches x 21 feet 9 inches x 20 feet 10 inches
Gift of the Burnett Foundation in Honor of Michael Auping
© 2002 Richard Serra
BIGHT 1 - 2011
Etching
Dimensions: 68,5 x 56 cm
© Galerie -
Lelong Paris
COURTAULD TRANSPARENCY
3 - 2013
Photograph: Robert
McKeever - Richard Serra
DEALER’S CHOICE 1996
Etching
© Galerie -
Lelong Paris
PATH AND EDGES 6 - 2007
Etching
Dimensions: 70 x 100cm
© Galerie - Lelong Paris
BAND 2006
Weatherproof Steel
Dimensions: Overall: 3.9 x 11.1 x 21.9 cm, Plate: 5.1 cm
© Richard Serra 2006
DOUBLE RIFT #6 - 2013
Paintstick on Handmade Paper
Dimensions: 214 × 611.5 × 9.5 cm
© Richard Serra. Courtesy the Artist
and Gagosian Gallery
Photography by Rob McKeever
DOUBLE RIFT #8 - 2013
Paintstick on Handmade Paper
Dimensions: 214.3 × 612.8 × 9.5 cm
© Richard Serra. Courtesy the artist
and Gagosian Gallery
Photography by Rob McKeever
DOUBLE RIFT #5 - 2012
Paintstick on Handmade Paper
Dimensions: 291.5 × 536.9 × 9.5 cm
© Richard Serra. Courtesy the Artist
and Gagosian Gallery
Photography by Rob McKeever
DEADWEIGHT V ( MEMPHIS ) 1991
Paintstik on Two Sheets of Paper
Mounted on Thin Fabric
Dimensions: Overall: 407.4 x 208 cm
Credit Line: Gift of Doris Lockhart
© 2015 Richard Serra / Artists Rights
Society (ARS), New York
DEADWEIGHT V 1991
ELEVATIONAL WEIGHTS BLACK MATTER 2010
NO MANDATORY PATRIOTISM 1989
Paintstik on Two Sheets of Paper
Dimensions:236.5 x 510.9 cm
Credit Line: Partial and Promised Gift
of UBS
© 2015 Richard Serra / Artists Rights
Society (ARS), New York
PATH AND EDGES 12 - 2007
Etching
Dimensions: 59,8 x 74,3cm
© Galerie -
Lelong Paris
PROMENADE NOTEBOOK IV - 2009
Etching
Dimensions: 40 x 30cm
© Galerie -
Lelong Paris
PATH AND EDGES 11 - 2007
Etching
Dimensions: 59,7 x 75cm
© Galerie -
Lelong Paris
BACKDOOR PIPELINE 2010
Weatherproof Steel
Dimensions: 380 × 1410 × 230 cm
Photo by Mike Bruce © Richard Serra,
Courtesy Gagosian Gallery
INTERVALS 2013
Weatherproof Steel, 24 Plates
Dimensions: 182.9 × 853.4 × 1447.8 cm
© Richard Serra. Photography by Rob
McKeever
INTERSECTION II, 1992 - 1993
Weatherproof Steel, Four Identical
Conical Sections
Dimensions: Two: 13' 1 1/2" High x 51'
9" Along the Chord x 2 1/8" Thick,
Two: 13' 1 1/2" High x 50' 9"
Along the Chord x 2 1/8" Thick,
The Museum of Modern Art, New York,
Gift of Jo Carole and Ronald S. Lauder,
© 2007 Richard Serra
THE MATTER OF TIME 2005
The Matter of
Time enables the spectator to perceive the evolution of the artist's
sculpted forms, from his relatively simple double ellipse to the more complex
spiral. The final two works in this evolution are built from sections of
toruses and spheres to create environments with differing effects on the
viewer's movement and perception. Shifting in unexpected ways as viewers walk
in and around them, these sculptures create a dizzying, unforgettable sensation
of space in motion. The entirety of the room is part of the sculptural field:
As with his other multipart sculptures, the artist purposefully organizes the
works to move the viewer through them and their surrounding space. The layout
of works in the gallery creates passages of space that are distinctly different—narrow
and wide, compressed and elongated, modest and towering—and always
unanticipated. There is also the progression of time. There is the
chronological time it takes to walk through and view The Matter of Time,
between the beginning and end of the visit. And there is the experiential time,
the fragments of visual and physical memory that linger and recombine and
replay.
TORQUED ELLIPSE 2003-2004
Weathering Steel
Dimensions: 4.27 x 8.31 x 8.84 m; Plate Thickness:
5 cm
Credit Line: Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa
TORQUED SPIRAL ( CLOSED OPEN CLOSED
OPEN CLOSED ) 2003
Weathering Steel
Dimensions: 4 x 13.1 x 14.1 m; Plate Thickness: 5
cm
Credit Line: Guggenheim Bilbao Museoa
© 2012
Richard Serra/Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York
TORQUED TORUS INVERSION 2006
Weatherproof Steel, Two Torqued Toruses
Dimensions: Each Overall: 12' 9" x 36'
1" x 58' 9", Plate: 2" Thick
Collection of the Artist, © 2007
Richard Serra, Collection of the Artist
JOE 2009
JOE 2009
CYCLE 2011
Weatherproof Steel
Dimensions: 1889.8 × 1706.9 × 426.7 cm
© Richard Serra. Courtesy Gagosian
Gallery. Photo by Lorenz Kienzle
DOUBLE TORQEUD ELLIPSE II – 1998
B
RICHARD SERRA
Richard Serra was born in 1939 in San Francisco. While working in steel mills
to support himself, Serra attended the University of California at Berkeley and
Santa Barbara from 1957 to 1961, receiving a BA in English literature. He then
studied as a painter at Yale University, New Haven, from 1961 to 1964,
completing his BFA and MFA there. While at Yale, Serra worked with Josef Albers on
his book The Interaction of
Color (1963). During the early 1960s, he came into contact with Philip
Guston, Robert Rauschenberg, Ad Reinhardt, and Frank Stella. In 1964 and 1965
Serra received a Yale Traveling Fellowship and traveled to Paris, where he
frequently visited the reconstruction of Constantin Brancusi’s studio at the
Musée National d’Art Moderne. He spent much of the following year in Florence
on a Fulbright grant and traveled throughout southern Europe and northern
Africa. The young artist was given his first solo exhibition at Galleria La
Salita, Rome, in 1966. Later that year, he moved to New York where his circle
of friends included Carl Andre, Walter De Maria, Eva Hesse, Sol LeWitt, and
Robert Smithson.
In 1966 Serra made his first sculptures out of nontraditional materials such as
fiberglass and rubber. From 1968 to 1970 he executed a series
of Splashpieces, in which molten lead was splashed or cast into the
junctures between floor and wall. Serra had his first solo exhibition in the
United States at the Leo Castelli Warehouse, New York. By 1969 he had begun
the Prop pieces, whose parts are not welded together or otherwise
attached but are balanced solely by forces of weight and gravity. That year, Serra
was included in Nine Young Artists: Theodoron
Awards at the Solomon R. Guggenheim Museum, New York. He produced the
first of his numerous short films in 1968 and in the early 1970s experimented
with video. The Pasadena Art Museum organized a solo exhibition of Serra’s work
in 1970, and in the same year he received a John Simon Guggenheim Memorial
Foundation fellowship. That year, he helped Smithson execute Spiral
Jetty at the Great Salt Lake in Utah; Serra, however, was less intrigued
by the vast American landscape than by urban sites, and in 1970 he installed a
piece on a dead-end street in the Bronx. He received the Skowhegan Medal for
Sculpture in 1975 and traveled to Spain to study Mozarabic architecture in
1982.Serra was honored with solo exhibitions at the Kunsthalle Tübingen, Germany, in 1978; the Musée National d’Art Moderne, Paris, in 1984; the Museum Haus Lange, Krefeld, Germany, in 1985; and the Museum of Modern Art, New York, in 1986. The 1990s saw further honors for Serra’s work: a retrospective of his drawings at the Bonnefantenmuseum, Maastricht; the Wilhelm Lehmbruck prize for sculpture in Duisburg in 1991; and the following year, a retrospective at Museo Nacional Centro de Arte Reina Sofía, Madrid. In 1993 Serra was elected a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. In 1994 he was awarded the Praemium Imperiale by the Japan Art Association and an Honorary Doctor of Fine Arts degree from the California College of the Arts, Oakland. Serra has continued to exhibit in both group and solo shows in such venues as Leo Castelli Gallery and Gagosian Gallery, New York. He continues to produce large-scale steel structures for sites throughout the world, and has become particularly renowned for his monumental arcs, spirals, and ellipses, which engage the viewer in an altered experience of space. From 1997 to 1998 his Torqued Ellipses (1997) were exhibited at and acquired by the Dia Center for the Arts, New York. In 2005 eight major works by Serra were installed permanently at Guggenheim Museum Bilbao, and in 2007 the Museum of Modern Art in New York mounted a major retrospective of his work. Serra lives outside New York City and in Nova Scotia.